GIVING UP DARWIN
By: David Gelernter
David Gelernter is professor of computer
science at Yale University, chief scientist at Mirror Worlds Technologies, and
member of the National Council of the Arts.
[[In my opinion, required
reading. DG]]
Darwinian evolution is a
brilliant and beautiful scientific theory. Once it was a daring guess. Today it
is basic to the credo that defines the modern worldview. Accepting the theory
as settled truth—no more subject to debate than the earth being round or the
sky blue or force being mass times acceleration—certifies that you are devoutly
orthodox in your scientific views; which in turn is an essential first step
towards being taken seriously in any part of modern intellectual life. But what
if Darwin was wrong?
Like so many others, I grew up
with Darwin’s theory, and had always believed it was true. I had heard doubts
over the years from well-informed, sometimes brilliant people, but I had my
hands full cultivating my garden, and it was easier to let biology take care of
itself. But in recent years, reading and discussion have shut that road down
for good.
This is sad. It is no victory of
any sort for religion. It is a
defeat for human ingenuity. It means one less beautiful idea in our world, and
one more hugely difficult and important problem back on mankind’s to-do list.
But we each need to make our peace with the facts, and not try to make life on
earth simpler than it really is.
Charles Darwin explained
monumental change by making one basic assumption—all life-forms descend from a
common ancestor—and adding two simple processes anyone can understand: random,
heritable variation and natural selection. Out of these simple ingredients,
conceived to be operating blindly over hundreds of millions of years, he
conjured up change that seems like
the deliberate unfolding of a grand plan, designed and carried out with
superhuman genius. Could nature really have pulled out of its hat the invention
of life, of increasingly sophisticated life-forms and, ultimately, the
unique-in-the-cosmos (so far as we know) human mind—given no strategy but trial
and error? The mindless accumulation of small changes? It is an astounding
idea. Yet Darwin’s brilliant and lovely theory explains how it could have happened.
Its beauty is important. Beauty
is often a telltale sign of truth. Beauty is our guide to the intellectual
universe—walking beside us through the uncharted wilderness, pointing us in the
right direction, keeping us on track—most of the time.
Demolishing a Worldview
There’s no reason to doubt that
Darwin successfully explained the small adjustments by which an organism adapts
to local circumstances: changes to fur density or wing style or beak shape. Yet
there are many reasons to doubt whether he can answer the hard questions and
explain the big picture—not the fine-tuning of existing species but the
emergence of new ones. The origin of species is exactly what Darwin cannot explain.
Stephen Meyer’s thoughtful and
meticulous Darwin’s Doubt (2013)
convinced me that Darwin has failed. He cannot answer the big question. Two other books
are also essential: The
Deniable Darwinand Other Essays (2009), by David Berlinski,
and Debating Darwin’s Doubt (2015),
an anthology edited by David Klinghoffer, which collects some of the arguments
Meyer’s book stirred up. These three form a fateful battle group that most
people would rather ignore. Bringing to bear the work of many dozen scientists
over many decades, Meyer, who after a stint as a geophysicist in Dallas earned
a Ph.D. in History and Philosophy of Science from Cambridge and now directs the
Discovery Institute’s Center for Science and Culture, disassembles the theory
of evolution piece by piece. Darwin’s
Doubtis one of the most important books in a generation. Few
open-minded people will finish it with their faith in Darwin intact.
Meyer doesn’t only demolish
Darwin; he defends a replacement theory, intelligent design (I.D.). Although I
can’t accept intelligent design as Meyer presents it, he does show that it is a
plain case of the emperor’s new clothes: it says aloud what anyone who ponders
biology must think, at some point,
while sifting possible answers to hard questions. Intelligent design as Meyer
explains it never uses religious arguments, draws religious conclusions, or
refers to religion in any way. It does underline an obvious but important
truth: Darwin’s mission was exactly to explain the flagrant appearance of design in nature.
The religion is all on the other
side. Meyer and other proponents of I.D. are the dispassionate intellectuals
making orderly scientific arguments. Some I.D.-haters have shown themselves
willing to use any argument—fair or not, true or not, ad hominem or not—to keep
this dangerous idea locked in a box forever. They remind us of the extent to
which Darwinism is no longer just a scientific theory but the basis of a
worldview, and an emergency replacement religion for the many troubled souls
who need one.
As for Biblical religion, it
forces its way into the discussion although Meyer didn’t invite it, and neither
did Darwin. Some have always been bothered by the harm Darwin is said to have
done religion. His theory has been thought by some naïfs (fundamentalists as
well as intellectuals) to have shown or alleged that the Bible is wrong, and
Judeo-Christian religion bunk. But this view assumes a childishly primitive
reading of Scripture. Anyone can see that there are two different creation
stories in Genesis, one based on seven days, the other on the Garden of Eden.
When the Bible gives us two different versions of one story, it stands to
reason that the facts on which they disagree are without basic religious
significance. The facts on which they agree are
the ones that matter: God created the universe, and put man there for a reason.
Darwin has nothing to say on these or any other key religious issues.
Fundamentalists and intellectuals
might go on arguing these things forever. But normal people will want to come
to grips with Meyer and the downfall of a beautiful idea. I will mention
several of his arguments, one of them in (just a bit of)
detail. This is one of the most important intellectual issues of modern times,
and every thinking person has the right and duty to judge for himself.
Looking for Evidence
Darwin himself had reservations
about his theory, shared by some of the most important biologists of his time.
And the problems that worried him have only grown more substantial over the
decades. In the famous “Cambrian explosion” of around half a billion years ago,
a striking variety of new organisms—including the first-ever animals—pop up
suddenly in the fossil record over a mere 70-odd million years. This great
outburst followed many hundreds of millions of years of slow growth and scanty
fossils, mainly of single-celled organisms, dating back to the origins of life
roughly three and half billion years ago.
Darwin’s theory predicts that new
life forms evolve gradually from old ones in a constantly branching, spreading
tree of life. Those brave new Cambrian creatures must therefore have had
Precambrian predecessors, similar but not quite as fancy and sophisticated.
They could not have all blown out suddenly, like a bunch of geysers. Each must
have had a closely related predecessor, which must have had its own
predecessors: Darwinian evolution is gradual, step-by-step. All those
predecessors must have come together, further back, into a series of branches
leading down to the (long ago) trunk.
But those predecessors of the
Cambrian creatures are missing. Darwin himself was disturbed by their absence
from the fossil record. He believed they would turn up eventually. Some of his
contemporaries (such as the eminent Harvard biologist Louis Agassiz) held that
the fossil record was clear enough already, and showed that Darwin’s theory was
wrong. Perhaps only a few sites had been searched for fossils, but they had
been searched straight down. The Cambrian explosion had been unearthed, and
beneath those Cambrian creatures their Precambrian predecessors should have
been waiting—and weren’t. In fact, the fossil record as a whole lacked the
upward-branching structure Darwin predicted.
The trunk was supposed to branch
into many different species, each species giving rise to many genera, and
towards the top of the tree you would find so much diversity that you could
distinguish separate phyla—the large divisions (sponges, mosses, mollusks,
chordates, and so on) that comprise the kingdoms of animals, plants, and
several others—take your pick. But, as Berlinski points out, the fossil record
shows the opposite: “representatives of separate phyla appearing first followed
by lower-level diversification on those basic themes.” In general, “most
species enter the evolutionary order fully formed and then depart unchanged.”
The incremental development of new species is largely not there. Those missing
pre-Cambrian organisms have still not turned up. (Although fossils are subject
to interpretation, and some biologists place pre-Cambrian life-forms closer
than others to the new-fangled Cambrian creatures.)
Some researchers have guessed
that those missing Precambrian precursors were too small or too soft-bodied to
have made good fossils. Meyer notes that fossil traces of ancient bacteria and
single-celled algae have been discovered: smallness per se doesn’t
mean that an organism can’t leave fossil traces—although the existence of
fossils depends on the surroundings in which the organism lived, and the
history of the relevant rock during the ages since it died. The story is
similar for soft-bodied organisms. Hard-bodied forms are more likely to be
fossilized than soft-bodied ones, but many fossils of soft-bodied organisms and
body parts do exist. Precambrian fossil deposits have been discovered in which
tiny, soft-bodied embryo sponges are preserved—but no predecessors to the
celebrity organisms of the Cambrian explosion.
This sort of negative evidence
can’t ever be conclusive. But the ever-expanding fossil archives don’t look
good for Darwin, who made clear and concrete predictions that have (so far)
been falsified—according to many reputable paleontologists, anyway. When does
the clock run out on those predictions? Never. But any thoughtful person must
ask himself whether scientists today are looking for evidence that bears on
Darwin, or looking to explain away evidence that contradicts him. There are
some of each. Scientists are only human, and their thinking (like everyone
else’s) is colored by emotion.
The Advent of Molecular Biology
Darwin’s main problem, however,
is molecular biology. There was no such thing in his own time. We now see from
inside what he could only see from outside, as if he had developed a theory of
mobile phone evolution without knowing that there were computers and software
inside or what the digital revolution was all about. Under the circumstances,
he did brilliantly.
Biology in his time was for
naturalists, not laboratory scientists. Doctor Dolittle was a naturalist. (He
is the hero of the wonderful children’s books by Hugh Lofting, now
unfortunately nearing extinction.) The doctor loved animals and understood
them, and had a sharp eye for all of nature not too different from Wordsworth’s
or Goethe’s. But the character of the field has changed, and it’s not
surprising that old theories don’t necessarily still work.
Darwin’s theory is simple to
grasp; its simplicity is the heart of its brilliance and power. We all know
that variation occurs naturally among individuals of the same type—white or
black sheep, dove-gray versus off-white or pale beige pigeons, boring and
sullen undergraduates versus charming, lissome ones. We all know that many
variations have no effect on a creature’s prospects, but some do. A sheep born
with extra-warm wool will presumably do better at surviving a rough Scottish
winter than his normal-wooled friends. Such a sheep would be more likely than
normal sheep to live long enough to mate, and pass on its superior trait to the
next generation. Over millions of years, small good-for-survival variations accumulate,
and eventually (says Darwin) you have a brand new species. The same mechanism
naturally favors genes that are right for the local environment—warm wool in
Scotland, light and comfortable wool for the tropics, other varieties for
mountains and deserts. Thus one species (your standard sheep) might eventually
become four specialized ones. And thus new species should develop from old in
the upward-branching tree pattern Darwin described.
The advent of molecular biology
made it possible to transform Darwinism into Neo-Darwinism. The new version
explains (it doesn’t merely cite) natural variation, as the consequence of
random change or mutation to the genetic information within cells that deal
with reproduction. Those cells can pass genetic change onward to the next
generation, thus changing—potentially—the future of the species and not just
one individual’s career.
The engine that powers
Neo-Darwinian evolution is pure chance and lots of time. By filling in the
details of cellular life, molecular biology makes it possible to estimate the
power of that simple mechanism. But what does generating
new forms of life entail? Many biologists agree that
generating a new shape of protein is the essence of
it. Only if Neo-Darwinian evolution is creative enough to do that is it capable
of creating new life-forms and pushing evolution forward.
Proteins are the special ops
forces (or maybe the Marines) of living cells, except that they are common
instead of rare; they do all the heavy lifting, all the tricky and critical
assignments, in a dazzling range of roles. Proteins called enzymes catalyze all
sorts of reactions and drive cellular metabolism. Other proteins (such as
collagen) give cells shape and structure, like tent poles but in far more
shapes. Nerve function, muscle function, and photosynthesis are all driven by
proteins. And in doing these jobs and many others, the actual, 3-D shape of the protein molecule
is important.
So, is the simple neo-Darwinian
mechanism up to this task? Are random mutation plus natural selection
sufficient to create new protein shapes?
Mutations
How to make proteins is our first
question. Proteins are chains: linear sequences of atom-groups, each bonded to
the next. A protein molecule is based on a chain of amino acids; 150 elements
is a “modest-sized” chain; the average is 250. Each link is chosen, ordinarily,
from one of 20 amino acids. A chain of amino acids is a polypeptide—“peptide”
being the type of chemical bond that joins one amino acid to the next. But this
chain is only the starting point: chemical forces among the links make parts of
the chain twist themselves into helices; others straighten out, and then,
sometimes, jackknife repeatedly, like a carpenter’s rule, into flat sheets.
Then the whole assemblage folds itself up like a complex sheet of origami
paper. And the actual 3-D shape of
the resulting molecule is (as I have said) important.
Imagine a 150-element protein as
a chain of 150 beads, each bead chosen from 20 varieties. But: only certain
chains will work. Only certain bead combinations will form themselves into
stable, useful, well-shaped proteins.
So how hard is it to build a useful,
well-shaped protein? Can you throw a bunch of amino acids together and assume
that you will get something good? Or must you choose each element of the chain
with painstaking care? It happens to be very hard
to choose the right beads.
Inventing a new protein means
inventing a new gene. (Enter, finally, genes, DNA etc., with suitable fanfare.)
Genes spell out the links of a protein chain, amino acid by amino acid. Each
gene is a segment of DNA, the world’s most admired macromolecule. DNA, of
course, is the famous double helix or spiral staircase, where each step is a
pair of nucleotides. As you read the nucleotides along one edge of the staircase
(sitting on one step and bumping your way downwards to the next and the next),
each group of three nucleotides along the way specifies an amino acid. Each
three-nucleotide group is a codon, and the correspondence between codons and
amino acids is the genetic code. (The four nucleotides in DNA are abbreviated
T, A, C and G, and you can look up the code in a high school textbook: TTA and
TTC stand for phenylalanine, TCT for serine, and so on.)
Your task is to invent a new gene
by mutation—by the accidental change
of one codon to a different codon. You have two possible starting points for
this attempt. You could mutate an existing gene, or mutate gibberish. You have
a choice because DNA actually consists of valid genes separated by long
sequences of nonsense. Most biologists think that the nonsense sequences are the
main source of new genes. If you tinker with a valid gene, you will almost
certainly make it worse—to the point where its protein misfires and endangers
(or kills) its organism—long before you start making it better. The gibberish
sequences, on the other hand, sit on the sidelines without making proteins, and
you can mutate them, so far as we know, without endangering anything. The
mutated sequence can then be passed on to the next generation, where it can be
mutated again. Thus mutations can accumulate on the sidelines without affecting
the organism. But if you mutate your way to an actual, valid new gene, your new
gene can create a new protein and thereby, potentially, play a role in
evolution.
Mutations themselves enter the picture
when DNA splits in half down the center of the staircase, thereby allowing the
enclosing cell to split in half, and the encompassing organism to grow. Each
half-staircase summons a matching set of nucleotides from the surrounding
chemical soup; two complete new DNA molecules emerge. A mistake in this elegant
replication process—the wrong nucleotide answering the call, a nucleotide
typo—yields a mutation, either to a valid blueprint or a stretch of gibberish.
Building a Better Protein
Now at last we are ready to take
Darwin out for a test drive. Starting with 150 links of gibberish, what are the
chances that we can mutate our way to a useful new shape of protein? We can ask
basically the same question in a more manageable way: what are the chances that
a random 150-link sequence will create such a protein? Nonsense sequences are
essentially random. Mutations are random. Make random changes to a random
sequence and you get another random sequence. So, close your eyes, make 150
random choices from your 20 bead boxes and string up your beads in the order in
which you chose them. What are the odds that you will come up with a useful new
protein?
It’s easy to see that the total
number of possible sequences is immense.
It’s easy to believe (although non-chemists must take their colleagues’ word
for it) that the subset of useful sequences—sequences
that create real, usable proteins—is, in comparison, tiny. But we must know how
immense and how tiny.
The total count of possible 150-link chains,
where each link is chosen separately from 20 amino acids, is 20^150. In other words, many. 20^150 roughly
equals 10^195, and there are only 10^80 atoms in the universe.
What proportion of these many
polypeptides are useful proteins? Douglas Axe did a series of experiments to
estimate how many 150-long chains are capable of stable folds—of reaching the
final step in the protein-creation process (the folding) and of holding their
shapes long enough to be useful. (Axe is a distinguished biologist with
five-star breeding: he was a graduate student at Caltech, then joined the
Centre for Protein Engineering at Cambridge. The biologists whose work Meyer
discusses are mainly first-rate Establishment scientists.) He estimated that,
of all 150-link amino acid sequences, 1 in 10^74 will
be capable of folding into a stable protein. To say that your chances are 1 in
10^74 is no different, in
practice, from saying that they are zero. It’s not surprising that your chances
of hitting a stable protein that performs some useful function, and might therefore play
a part in evolution, are even smaller. Axe puts them at 1 in 10^77.
In other words: immense is so
big, and tiny is so small, that neo-Darwinian evolution is—so far—a dead loss. Try to mutate
your way from 150 links of gibberish to a working, useful protein and you are
guaranteed to fail. Try it with ten mutations, a thousand, a million—you fail.
The odds bury you. It can’t be done.
A Bad Bet
But neo-Darwinianism understands that mutations are rare, and
successful ones even scarcer. To balance that out, there are many organisms and
a staggering immensity of time. Your chances of winning might be infinitesimal.
But if you play the game often enough, you win in the end, right? After all, it
works for Powerball!
Do the numbers balance out? Is Neo-Darwinian evolution
plausible after all? Axe reasoned as follows. Consider the whole history of
living things—the entire group of every living organism ever. It is dominated
numerically by bacteria. All other organisms, from tangerine trees to coral
polyps, are only a footnote. Suppose, then, that every bacterium that has ever
lived contributes one mutation before its demise to the history of life. This
is a generous assumption; most bacteria pass on their genetic information
unchanged, unmutated. Mutations are the exception. In any case, there have
evidently been, in the whole history of life, around 10^40 bacteria—yielding
around 10^40 mutations under
Axe’s assumptions. That is a very large number of chances at any game. But
given that the odds each time are 1 to 10^77 against,
it is not large enough. The odds against blind Darwinian chance having turned
up even one mutation with the potential to push evolution forward are 10^40x(1/10^77)—10^40 tries, where your odds of success
each time are 1 in 10^77—which
equals 1 in 10^37. In practical
terms, those odds are still zero. Zero odds of producing a single promising
mutation in the whole history of life. Darwin loses.
His idea is still perfectly
reasonable in the abstract. But concretely, he is overwhelmed by numbers he
couldn’t possibly have foreseen: the ridiculously large number of amino-acid
chains relative to number of useful proteins. Those numbers transcend the
details of any particular set of estimates. The obvious fact is that genes, in
storing blueprints for the proteins that form the basis of cellular life,
encode an awe-inspiring amount of information. You don’t turn up a useful
protein merely by doodling on the back of an envelope, any more than you write
a Mozart aria by assembling three sheets of staff paper and scattering notes
around. Profound biochemical knowledge is somehow, in some sense, captured in
every description of a working protein. Where on earth did it all come from?
Neo-Darwinianism says that nature
simply rolls the dice, and if something useful emerges, great. Otherwise, try
again. But useful sequences are so gigantically rare that this answer simply
won’t work. Studies of the sort Meyer discusses show that Neo-Darwinism is the
quintessence of a bad bet.
The Great Darwinian Paradox
There are many other problems
besides proteins. One of the most basic, and the last I’ll mention here, calls
into question the whole idea of gene mutations driving macro-evolution—the
emergence of new forms of organism, versus mere variation on existing forms.
To help create a brand new form
of organism, a mutation must affect a gene that does its job early and controls
the expression of other genes that come into play later on as the organism
grows. But mutations to these early-acting “strategic” genes, which create the
big body-plan changes required by macro-evolution, seem to be invariably fatal.
They kill off the organism long before it can reproduce. This is common sense.
Severely deformed creatures don’t ever seem fated to lead the way to glorious
new forms of life. Instead, they die young.
Evidently there are a total of no examples in the literature
of mutations that affect early development and the body plan as a whole and are not fatal. The German geneticists
Christiane Nüsslein-Volhard and Eric Wieschaus won the Nobel Prize in 1995 for
the “Heidelberg screen,” an exhaustive investigation of every observable or
inducible mutation of Drosophila
melanogaster (the same patient, long-suffering fruit fly I
meddled with relentlessly in an undergraduate genetics lab in the 1970s). “[W]e
think we’ve hit all the genes required to specify the body plan of Drosophila,” said Wieschaus in
answering a question after a talk. Not one, he continued, is “promising as raw
materials for macroevolution”—because mutations in them all killed off the fly
long before it could mate. If an exhaustive search rules out every last plausible gene as a
candidate for large-scale Drosophila evolution, where does that leave Darwin?
Wieschaus continues: “What are—or
what would be—the right mutations for
major evolutionary change? And we don’t know the answer to that.”
There is a general principle
here, similar to the earlier principle that the number of useless polypeptides
crushes the number of useful ones. The Georgia Tech geneticist John F. McDonald
calls this one a “great Darwinian paradox.” Meyer explains: “genes that are
obviously variable within natural populations seem to affect only minor aspects
of form and function—while those genes that govern major changes, the very
stuff of macroevolution, apparently do not vary or vary only to the detriment
of the organism.” The philosopher of biology Paul Nelson summarizes the
body-plan problem:
Research on animal development
and macroevolution over the last thirty years—research done from within the
neo-Darwinian framework—has shown that the neo-Darwinian explanation for the
origin of new body plans is overwhelmingly likely to be false—and for reasons
that Darwin himself would have understood.
Darwin would easily have
understood that minor mutations are common but can’t create significant
evolutionary change; major mutations are rare and fatal.
It can hardly be surprising that
the revolution in biological knowledge over the last half-century should call
for a new understanding of the origin of species.
Darwin’s Limits
Intelligent Design, as Meyer
describes it, is a simple and direct response to a specific event, the Cambrian
explosion. The theory suggests that an intelligent cause intervened to create
this extraordinary outburst. By “intelligent” Meyer understands “conscious”;
the theory suggests nothing more about the designer. But where is the evidence?
To Meyer and other proponents, that is like asking—after you have come across a
tree that is split vertically down the center and half burnt up—“but where is
the evidence of a lightning
strike?” The exceptional intricacy of living things, and their elaborate
mechanisms for fitting precisely into their natural surroundings, seemed to cry
out for an intelligent designer long before molecular biology and biochemistry.
Darwin’s theory, after all, is an attempt to explain “design without a
designer,” according to evolutionary biologist Francisco Ayala. An intelligent
designer might seem more necessary than ever now that we understand so much
cellular biology, and the impossibly long odds facing any attempt to design
proteins by chance, or assemble the regulatory mechanisms that control the life
cycle of a cell.
Meyer doesn’t reject Darwinian
evolution. He only rejects it as a sufficient theory of life as we know it.
He’s made a painstaking investigation of Darwin’s theory and has rejected it
for many good reasons that he has carefully explained. He didn’t rush to
embrace intelligent design. Just the opposite. But the explosion of detailed,
precise information that was necessary to build the brand-new Cambrian
organisms, and the fact that the information was encoded,
represented symbolically, in DNA nucleotides, suggests to Meyer that an
intelligent designer must have been responsible. “Our uniform experience of
cause and effect shows that intelligent design is the only known cause of the origin
of large amounts of functionally specified digital information,” he writes.
(“Digital” is confusing here; it only means information represented by a
sequence of symbols.)
Was the Cambrian Explosion unique in some absolute sense, or
was it the extreme endpoint of a spectrum? After all, there were infusions of
new genetic information before and after. Meyer himself writes that “the sudden
appearance of the Cambrian animals was merely the most outstanding instance of
a pattern of discontinuity that extends throughout the geologic column.”
It’s not easy to decide whether
something stands alone or at the far end of some spectrum. Consider Meyer’s
“functionally specified digital information.” Information intended for one
specific purpose and spelled out in a sequence of symbols is a rare bird in
nature. It’s an outlier in the world of intelligence, too. We nearly always
communicate in symbols that are used for many purposes;
it’s hard for us to confine any symbol system to a single purpose. Even digits
are used to represent numbers of many kinds, to express order as well as
magnitude, as names (2001: A Space Odyssey) or parts of
English phrases (“second rate”). A line of music can be heard in the head,
hummed or sung, played on a zither or performed by a large orchestra. Or it can
serve as a single graphic symbol meaning “music.” But the genetic code is used
to specify the structure of certain molecules only(albeit
in a series of separate steps and information-transfers within the cell).
Nature, for its part, encodes information in many ways: airborne scents are
important to bees, butterflies, elephants seeking to mate, birds avoiding
trouble, and untold other creatures. The scent is a symbol; it’s not the scent that threatens the bird.
Channels in sand dunes encode information about the passing breezes—and so on.
There are endless examples—none approaching the sophistication and complexity
of DNA coding.
If Meyer were invoking a single intervention
by an intelligent designer at the invention of life, or of consciousness, or
rationality, or self-aware consciousness, the idea might seem more natural. But
then we still haven’t explained the Cambrian explosion. An intelligent designer
who interferes repeatedly, on the other hand, poses an even harder problem of
explaining why he chose to act when he did. Such a cause would necessarily have
some sense of the big picture of life on earth. What was his strategy? How did
he manage to back himself into so many corners, wasting energy on so many
doomed organisms? Granted, they might each have contributed genes to our common
stockpile—but could hardly have done so in the most efficient way. What was his
purpose? And why did he do such an awfully slipshod job? Why are we so disease
prone, heartbreak prone, and so on? An intelligent designer makes perfect sense
in the abstract. The real challenge is how to fit this designer into life as we
know it. Intelligent design might well be the ultimate answer. But as a theory,
it would seem to have a long way to go.
A Final Challenge
I might, myself, expect to find
the answer in a phenomenon that acts as if it were a new and (thus far) unknown
force or field associated with consciousness. I’d expect complex biochemistry
to be consistently biased in the direction that leads closer to consciousness,
as gravitation biases motion towards massive objects. I have no evidence for
this idea. It’s just the way biology seems to work.
Although Stephen Meyer’s book is
a landmark in the intellectual history of Darwinism, the theory will be with us
for a long time, exerting enormous cultural force. Darwin is no Newton.
Newton’s physics survived Einstein and will always survive, because it explains
the cases that dominate all of space-time except for the extreme ends of the
spectrum, at the very smallest and largest scales. It’s just these most
important cases, the ones we see all around us, that Darwin cannot explain. Yet his theory
does explain cases of real significance. And Darwin’s intellectual daring will
always be inspiring. The man will always be admired.
He now poses a final challenge. Whether biology will rise to
this last one as well as it did to the first, when his theory upset every apple
cart, remains to be seen. How cleanly and quickly can the field get over
Darwin, and move on?—with due allowance for every Darwinist’s having to study
all the evidence for himself? There is one of most important questions facing
science in the 21st century.