What Does Quantum Physics Actually Tell Us About the World?
By James Gleick
https://www.nytimes.com/2018/05/08/books/review/adam-becker-what-is-real.html
May 8,
2018
WHAT
IS REAL?
The Unfinished Quest for the Meaning of Quantum Physics
By Adam Becker
370 pp. Basic Books. $32.
The Unfinished Quest for the Meaning of Quantum Physics
By Adam Becker
370 pp. Basic Books. $32.
Are
atoms real? Of course they are. Everybody believes in atoms, even people who
don’t believe in evolution or climate change. If we didn’t have atoms, how
could we have atomic bombs? But you can’t see an atom directly. And even though
atoms were first conceived and named by ancient Greeks, it was not until the
last century that they achieved the status of actual physical entities — real
as apples, real as the moon.
The
first proof of atoms came from 26-year-old Albert Einstein in 1905, the same
year he proposed his theory of special relativity. Before that, the atom served
as an increasingly useful hypothetical construct. At the same time, Einstein
defined a new entity: a particle of light, the “light quantum,” now called the
photon. Until then, everyone considered light to be a kind of wave. It didn’t
bother Einstein that no one could observe this new thing. “It is the theory
which decides what we can observe,” he said.
Which brings us to
quantum theory. The physics of atoms and their ever-smaller constituents and
cousins is, as Adam Becker reminds us more than once in his new book, “What Is
Real?,” “the most successful theory in all of science.” Its predictions are
stunningly accurate, and its power to grasp the unseen ultramicroscopic world
has brought us modern marvels. But there is a problem: Quantum theory is, in a
profound way, weird. It defies our common-sense intuition about what things are
and what they can do.
“Figuring
out what quantum physics is saying about the world has been hard,” Becker says,
and this understatement motivates his book, a thorough, illuminating
exploration of the most consequential controversy raging in modern science.
The debate over the
nature of reality has been growing in intensity for more than a half-century;
it generates conferences and symposiums and enough argumentation to fill entire
journals. Before he died, Richard Feynman, who understood quantum theory as
well as anyone, said, “I still get nervous with it...I cannot define the real
problem, therefore I suspect there’s no real problem, but I’m not sure there’s
no real problem.” The problem is not with using the theory — making
calculations, applying it to engineering tasks — but in understanding what it
means. What does it tell us about the world?
From
one point of view, quantum physics is just a set of formalisms, a useful tool
kit. Want to make better lasers or transistors or television sets? The
Schrödinger equation is your friend. The trouble starts only when you step back
and ask whether the entities implied by the equation can really exist. Then you
encounter problems that can be described in several familiar ways:
Wave-particle
duality. Everything there is — all matter and energy, all known forces —
behaves sometimes like waves, smooth and continuous, and sometimes like
particles, rat-a-tat-tat. Electricity flows through wires, like a fluid, or
flies through a vacuum as a volley of individual electrons. Can it be both
things at once?
The
uncertainty principle. Werner Heisenberg famously discovered that when you
measure the position (let’s say) of an electron as precisely as you can, you
find yourself more and more in the dark about its momentum. And vice versa. You
can pin down one or the other but not both.
The measurement problem.
Most of quantum mechanics deals with probabilities rather than certainties. A
particle has a probability of appearing in a certain place. An unstable atom
has a probability of decaying at a certain instant. But when a physicist goes
into the laboratory and performs an experiment, there is a definite outcome.
The act of measurement — observation, by someone or something — becomes an
inextricable part of the theory.
The strange implication
is that the reality of the quantum world remains amorphous or indefinite until
scientists start measuring. Schrödinger’s cat, as you may have heard, is in a
terrifying limbo, neither alive nor dead, until someone opens the box to look.
Indeed, Heisenberg said that quantum particles “are not as real; they form a
world of potentialities or possibilities rather than one of things or facts.”
This is
disturbing to philosophers as well as physicists. It led Einstein to say in
1952, “The theory reminds me a little of the system of delusions of an
exceedingly intelligent paranoiac.”
So
quantum physics — quite unlike any other realm of science — has acquired its
own metaphysics, a shadow discipline tagging along like the tail of a comet.
You can think of it as an “ideological superstructure” (Heisenberg’s phrase).
This field is called quantum foundations, which is inadvertently ironic,
because the point is that precisely where you would expect foundations you
instead find quicksand.
Competing
approaches to quantum foundations are called “interpretations,” and nowadays
there are many. The first and still possibly foremost of these is the so-called
Copenhagen interpretation. “Copenhagen” is shorthand for Niels Bohr, whose
famous institute there served as unofficial world headquarters for quantum
theory beginning in the 1920s. In a way, the Copenhagen is an anti-interpretation.
“It is wrong to think that the task of physics is to find out how nature is,”
Bohr said. “Physics concerns what we can say about nature.Nothing is definite
in Bohr’s quantum world until someone observes it. Physics can help us order
experience but should not be expected to provide a complete picture of reality.
The popular four-word summary of the Copenhagen interpretation is: “Shut up and
calculate!”
For
much of the 20th century, when quantum physicists were making giant leaps in
solid-state and high-energy physics, few of them bothered much about
foundations. But the philosophical difficulties were always there, troubling
those who cared to worry about them.
Becker sides with the
worriers. He leads us through an impressive account of the rise of competing
interpretations, grounding them in the human stories, which are naturally messy
and full of contingencies. He makes a convincing case that it’s wrong to
imagine the Copenhagen interpretation as a single official or even coherent
statement. It is, he suggests, a “strange assemblage of claims.”
111Comments
The Times needs your voice. We welcome your on-topic commentary,
criticism and expertise.
An
American physicist, David Bohm, devised a radical alternative at midcentury,
visualizing “pilot waves” that guide every particle, an attempt to eliminate
the wave-particle duality. For a long time, he was mainly lambasted or ignored,
but variants of the Bohmian interpretation have supporters today. Other
interpretations rely on “hidden variables” to account for quantities presumed
to exist behind the curtain. Perhaps the most popular lately — certainly the
most talked about — is the “many-worlds interpretation”: Every quantum event is
a fork in the road, and one way to escape the difficulties is to imagine,
mathematically speaking, that each fork creates a new universe.
So in
this view, Schrödinger’s cat is alive and well in one universe while in another
she goes to her doom. And we, too, should imagine countless versions of
ourselves. Everything that can happen does happen, in one universe or another.
“The universe is constantly splitting into a stupendous number of branches,”
said the theorist Bryce DeWitt, “every quantum transition taking place on every
star, in every galaxy, in every remote corner of the universe is splitting our
local world on earth into myriads of copies of itself.”
This is
ridiculous, of course. “A heavy load of metaphysical baggage,” John Wheeler
called it. How could we ever prove or disprove such a theory? But if you think
the many-worlds idea is easily dismissed, plenty of physicists will beg to
differ. They will tell you that it could explain, for example, why quantum
computers (which admittedly don’t yet quite exist) could be so powerful: They
would delegate the work to their alter egos in other universes.
Is any
of this real? At the risk of spoiling its suspense, I will tell you that this
book does not propose a definite answer to its title question. You weren’t
counting on one, were you? The story is far from finished.
When scientists search
for meaning in quantum physics, they may be straying into a no-man’s-land
between philosophy and religion. But they can’t help themselves. They’re only
human. “If you were to watch me by day, you would see me sitting at my desk
solving Schrödinger’s equation...exactly like my colleagues,” says Sir Anthony
Leggett, a Nobel Prize winner and pioneer in superfluidity. “But occasionally
at night, when the full moon is bright, I do what in the physics community is
the intellectual equivalent of turning into a werewolf: I question whether
quantum mechanics is the complete and ultimate truth about the physical
universe.”
James Gleick