Is nature
continuous or discrete? How the atomist error was born
https://aeon.co/ideas/is-nature-continuous-or-discrete-how-the-atomist-error-was-born?utm_source=Aeon+Newsletter&utm_campaign=bb63ea6739-EMAIL_CAMPAIGN_2018_05_16&utm_medium=email&utm_term=0_411a82e59d-bb63ea6739-69543105
[[A little difficult, but an excellent example of how deep msitakes can go, and how subtle our world is - or I should say "looks" under this latest comment.]]
is associate professor
of philosophy at the University of Denver. His latest book is Lucretius I: An
Ontology of Motion (2018).
The modern idea
that nature is discrete originated in Ancient Greek atomism. Leucippus,
Democritus and Epicurus all argued that nature was composed of what they called
ἄτομος (átomos)
or ‘indivisible individuals’. Nature was, for them, the totality of discrete
atoms in motion. There was no creator god, no immortality of the soul, and
nothing static (except for the immutable internal nature of the atoms
themselves). Nature was atomic matter in motion and complex composition – no
more, no less.
Despite its
historical influence, however, atomism was eventually all but wiped out by
Platonism, Aristotelianism and the Christian tradition that followed throughout
the Middle Ages. Plato told his followers to destroy Democritus’ books whenever
they found them, and later the Christian tradition made good on this demand.
Today, nothing but a few short letters from Epicurus remain.
Atomism was not
finished, however. It reemerged in 1417, when an Italian book-hunter named
Poggio Bracciolini discovered a copy of an ancient poem in a remote
monastery: De Rerum Natura (On the Nature of Things),
written by Lucretius (c99-55 BCE), a Roman poet heavily influenced by
Epicurus. This book-length philosophical poem in epic verse puts forward the
most detailed and systematic account of ancient materialism that we’ve been
fortunate enough to inherit. In it, Lucretius advances a breathtakingly bold
theory on foundational issues in everything from physics to ethics, aesthetics,
history, meteorology and religion. Against the wishes and best efforts of the
Christian church, Bracciolini managed to get it into print, and it soon
circulated across Europe.
This book was one
of the most important sources of inspiration for the scientific revolution of
the 16th and 17th centuries. Nearly every Renaissance and Enlightenment
intellectual read it and became an atomist to some degree (they often made
allowances for God and the soul). Indeed, this is the reason why, to make a
long and important story very short, science and philosophy even today still
tend to look for and assume a fundamental discreteness in nature. Thanks in no
small part to Lucretius’ influence, the search for discreteness became part of
our historical DNA. The interpretive method and orientation of modern science
in the West literally owe their philosophical foundations to ancient atomism
via Lucretius’ little book on nature. Lucretius, as Stephen Greenblatt says in
his book The Swerve (2011), is ‘how the world became modern’.
There is a
problem, however. If this story is true, then modern Western thought is based
on a complete misreading of Lucretius’ poem. It was not a wilful misreading, of
course, but one in which readers committed the simple error of projecting what
little they knew second-hand about Greek atomism (mostly from the testimonia of
its enemies) onto Lucretius’ text. They assumed a closer relationship between
Lucretius’ work and that of his predecessors than actually exists. Crucially,
they inserted the words ‘atom’ and ‘particle’ into the translated text, even
though Lucretius never used them. Not even once! A rather odd omission for a
so-called ‘atomist’ to make, no? Lucretius could easily have used the Latin
words atomus (smallest particle) or particula (particle),
but he went out of his way not to. Despite his best efforts, however, the two
very different Latin terms he did use, corpora(matters) and rerum (things),
were routinely translated and interpreted as synonymous with discrete ‘atoms’.
Further, the
moderns either translated out or ignored altogether the nearly ubiquitous
language of continuum and folding used throughout his book, in phrases such as
‘solida primordia simplicitate’ (simplex continuum). As a rare breed of
scholar interested in both classical texts and quantum physics, the existence
of this material continuum in the original Latin struck me quite profoundly. I
have tried to show all of this in my
recent translation and commentary, Lucretius I: An Ontology of Motion (2018),
but here is the punchline: this simple but systematic and ubiquitous
interpretive error constitutes what might well be the single biggest mistake in
the history of modern science and philosophy.
This mistake sent
modern science and philosophy on a 500-year quest for what Sean Carroll in his
2012 book called the ‘particle at the end of the universe’. It gave birth to
the laudable virtues of various naturalisms and materialisms, but also to less
praiseworthy mechanistic reductionisms, patriarchal rationalisms, and the overt
domination of nature by humans, none of which can be found in Lucretius’
original Latin writings. What’s more, even when confronted with apparently
continuous phenomena such as gravity, electric and magnetic fields, and
eventually space-time, Isaac Newton, James Maxwell and even Albert Einstein
fell back on the idea of an atomistic ‘aether’ to explain them. All the way
back to the ancients, aether was thought to be a subtle fluid-like substance
composed of insensibly tiny particles. Today, we no longer believe in the
aether or read Lucretius as an authoritative scientific text. Yet in our own
way, we still confront the same problem of continuity vs discreteness
originally bequeathed to us by the moderns: in quantum physics.
Theoretical
physics today is at a critical turning point. General relativity and quantum
field theory are the two biggest parts of what physicists now call ‘the
standard model’, which has enjoyed incredible predictive success. The problem,
however, is that they have not yet been unified as two aspects of one
overarching theory. Most physicists think that such unification is only a
matter of time, even though the current theoretical frontrunners (string theory
and loop quantum gravity) have yet to produce experimental confirmations.
Quantum gravity
is of enormous importance. According to its proponents, it stands poised to
show the world that the ultimate fabric of nature (space-time) is not
continuous at all, but granular, and fundamentally
discrete. The atomist legacy might finally be secured, despite its origins in
an interpretive error.
There is just one
nagging problem: quantum field theory claims that all discrete quanta of energy
(particles) are merely the excitations or fluctuations in completely continuous
quantum fields. Fields are notfundamentally granular.
For quantum field theory, everything might be made of granules, but all
granules are made of folded-up continuous fields that we simply measure as
granular. This is what physicists call ‘perturbation theory’: the discrete
measure of that which is infinitely continuous and so ‘perturbs one’s complete
discrete measurement’, as Frank Close puts it in The Infinity Puzzle (2011).
Physicists also have a name for the sub-granular movement of this continuous
field: ‘vacuum fluctuations’. Quantum fields are nothing but matter in constant
motion (energy and momentum). They are therefore never ‘nothing’, but more like
a completely positive void (the flux of the vacuum itself) or an undulating
ocean (appropriately called ‘the Dirac sea’) in which all discrete things are
its folded-up bubbles washed ashore, as Carlo Rovelli puts it in Reality
Is Not What it Seems (2016). Discrete particles, in other words, are
folds in continuous fields.
The answer to the
central question at the heart of modern science, ‘Is nature continuous or
discrete?’ is as radical as it is simple. Space-time is not continuous because
it is made of quantum granules, but quantum granules are not discrete because
they are folds of infinitely continuous vibrating fields. Nature is thus not
simply continuous, but an enfolded continuum.
This brings us
right back to Lucretius and our original error. Working at once within and
against the atomist tradition, Lucretius put forward the first materialist
philosophy of an infinitely continuous nature in constant flux and motion.
Things, for Lucretius, are nothing but folds (duplex), pleats (plex),
bubbles or pores (foramina) in a single continuous fabric (textum)
woven by its own undulations. Nature is infinitely turbulent or perturbing, but
it also washes ashore, like the birth of Venus, in meta-stable forms – as
Lucretius writes in the opening lines of De Rerum Natura: ‘Without
you [Venus] nothing emerges into the sunlit shores of light.’ It has taken
2,000 years, but perhaps Lucretius has finally become our contemporary.